pregleda

Collected Papers of Clarence Irving Lewis


Cena:
1.999 din (Predmet je prodat)
Stanje: Polovan bez oštećenja
Garancija: Ne
Isporuka: Pošta
Post Express
Lično preuzimanje
Plaćanje: Tekući račun (pre slanja)
Lično
Grad: Novi Beograd,
Beograd-Novi Beograd
Prodavac

bibliofil1 (11230)

PREMIUM član
Član je postao Premium jer:
- ima 100 jedinstvenih pozitivnih ocena od kupaca,
- tokom perioda od 6 meseci uplati minimum 20.000 dinara na svoj Limundo račun.

100% pozitivnih ocena

Pozitivne: 23817

  Pošalji poruku

Svi predmeti člana


Kupindo zaštita

ISBN: Ostalo
Godina izdanja: .
Jezik: Engleski
Autor: Strani

Clarence Irving (C.I.) Lewis was perhaps the most important American academic philosopher active in the 1930s and 1940s. He made major contributions in epistemology and logic, and, to a lesser degree, ethics. Lewis was also a key figure in the rise of analytic philosophy in the United States, both through the development and influence of his own writings and through his influence, direct and indirect, on graduate students at Harvard, including some of the leading analytic philosophers of the last half of the 20th century.

Logic
Lewis studied logic under his eventual Ph.D. thesis supervisor, Josiah Royce, and is a principal architect of modern philosophical logic. In 1912, two years after the publication of the first volume of Principia Mathematica, Lewis began publishing articles[citation needed] taking exception to Principia` s pervasive use of material implication, more specifically, to Bertrand Russell`s reading of a→b as `a implies b.` Lewis restated this criticism in his reviews[citation needed] of both editions of Principia Mathematica. Lewis`s reputation as a promising young logician was soon assured.

Material implication (the rule of inference which claims that stating `P implies Q` is equivalent to stating `Q OR not P`) allows a true consequent to follow from a false antecedent (so if P is not true still Q may be true since you only stated what a true P implies, but did not state what is implied if P is untrue).

Lewis proposed to replace the usage of material implication during discussions involving logic with the term strict implication, by which a (contingently) false antecedent, which is false but could have been true, does not always strictly imply a (contingently) true consequent, which is true but could have been false. The same logical result is implied, but in a clearer and more explicit way. Stating strictly that P implies Q is explicitly not stating what the untrue P implies. And therefor if P is not true, Q may be true, but may be false as well.[11]

As opposed to material implication, in strict implication the statement is not primitive - it is not defined in positive terms, but rather in the combined terms of negation, conjunction, and a prefixed unary intensional modal operator, {\displaystyle \Diamond }\Diamond . The following is its formal definition:

If X is a formula with a classical bivalent truth value
(which must be either true or false),
then {\displaystyle \Diamond }\Diamond X can be read as `X is possibly true`.[11]
Lewis then defined `A strictly implies B` as `{\displaystyle \neg \Diamond }\neg \Diamond (A{\displaystyle \land \neg }{\displaystyle \land \neg }B)`.[12] Lewis`s strict implication is now a historical curiosity, but the formal modal logic in which he grounded that notion is the ancestor of all modern work on the subject. Lewis` {\displaystyle \Diamond }\Diamond notation is still standard, but current practice usually takes its dual, the square notation {\displaystyle \square }\square , meaning `necessity`, which is stating a primitive notion, while the diamond notation, {\displaystyle \Diamond }\Diamond , is left as a defined (derived) meaning. With square notation `A strictly implies B` is simply written as {\displaystyle \square }\square (A→B), which states explicitly that we are only implying the truth of B when A is true, and we are not implying anything about when B can be false, nor what A implies if it is false, in which case B can be false or B can just as well be true.[11]

His first published monograph about advances in logic since the time of Leibniz, A Survey of Symbolic Logic (1918), culminating a series of articles written since 1900, went out of print after selling several hundred copies. At the time of its publication, it included the only discussion in English of the logical writings of Charles Sanders Peirce.[13] This book followed Russell`s 1900 monograph on Leibnitz, and in later editions he removed a section that seemed similar to it.[14][15]

Lewis went on to devise modal logic which he described in his next book Symbolic Logic (1932) as possible formal analyses of the alethic modalities, modes of logical truth such as necessity, possibility and impossibility.

Several amended versions of his first book `A Survey of Symbolic Logic` have been written over the years, designated as S1 to S5, the last two, S4 and S5, generated much mathematical and philosophical interest, sustained to the present day and are the beginnings of what became the field of normal modal logic.[11]

Pragmatist but no positivist
Around 1930, with the introduction of logical empiricism to America by German and Austrian philosophers fleeing Europe under Nazi Germany, American philosophy went through a turning point.

This new doctrine, with its emphasis on scientific models of knowledge and on the logical analysis of meaning, soon became dominant, challenging American philosophers such as Lewis who held a naturalistic or pragmatic approach.[16]

Lewis was perceived as a logical empiricist, but actually differed with it on some major points, rejecting logical positivism, which is the notion that all genuine knowledge is derived solely from sensory experience as interpreted through reason and logic, and rejecting physicalism with its notion that the mind along with its experience is actually equivalent to physical entities such as the brain and the body. He held that experience should be analyzed separately, and that semiotic value does have cognitive significance.[16]

Reflecting on the differences between pragmatism and positivism, Lewis devised the notion of cognitive structure, concluding that any significant knowledge must come from experience. Semiotic value, accordingly, is the way of representing this knowledge, which is stored for deciding future conduct.

Charles Sanders Peirce the founder of pragmaticism saw the world as a system of signs. Therefore scientific research was a branch of semiotics, primarily needing to be analyzed and justified in semiotic terms, before actually conducting any kind of experiment, and the meaning of meaning must be understood before anything else could be `explained`. This included analyzing and studying what experience itself is.[17] In Mind and the World Order (1929) Lewis explained that Peirce`s `pragmatic test` of significance should be understood with Peirce`s own limitation which prescribed meaning only to what makes a verfiable difference in experience although experience is subjective.

A year later, in Pragmatism and Current Thought (1930) he repeated this but emphasized the subjectiveness of experience. Concepts, according to Lewis` explanation of Pierce, are abstractions in which the experience is to be considered, rather than any `factual` or `immediate` truth.[18]

The validation of the perceived experiences are achieved by doing comparison tests. For example if one person perceives time or weight as double that of the other`s perception, the two perceptions are never truly comparable. Thus a concept is a relational pattern.

Still, by checking the physical attributes which each of the two people assign to their experiences, in this case the weight and time in physical units, it is possible to analyze some part of the experience, and one should not discard that very important aspect of the world as it is experienced.

In one sense, that of connotation, a concept strictly comprises nothing but an abstract configuration of relations. In another sense, its denotation or empirical application, this meaning is vested in a process which characteristically begins with something given and ends with something done in the operation which translates a presented datum into an instrument of prediction and control.

Thus knowledge begins and ends in experience, keeping in mind that the beginning and ending experiences differ.

Furthermore, according to Lewis` interpretation of Pierce, knowledge of something requires that the verifying experience itself be actually experienced as well.

Thus, for the pragmatist, verifiability as an operational definition (or test) of the empirical meaning of a statement requires that the speaker know how to apply that statement, when not to apply it, and that the speaker will be able to trace the consequences of the statement in situations both real and hypothetical.

Lewis firmly objected to the positivist interpretation of value statements as being merely `expressive`, devoid of any cognitive content.

In his 1946 essay Logical Positivism and Pragmatism Lewis set out both his concept of sense meaning, and his thesis that valuation is a form of empirical cognition. He disagreed with verificationism, and preferred the term empirical meaning. Claiming that pragmatism and logical positivism are forms of empiricism.

Lewis argued that there is a deep difference between the seemingly similar concepts of pragmatic meaning and the logical-positivist requirement of verification.

According to Lewis, pragmatism ultimately bases its understanding of meaning on conceivable experience, while positivism reduces the relation between meaning and experience to a matter of logical form. Thus, according to Lewis, the positivist view precisely omits the necessary empirical meaning as it would be called by the pragmatist.

Specifying which observational statements follow from a given sentence, helps us determine the empirical meaning of the given sentence only if the observation statements themselves have an already understood meaning in terms of the experience which the observation statements refer to.

According to Lewis, the logical positivists failed to distinguish between `linguistic` meaning - the logical relations among terms, and `empirical` meaning - the relation that expressions must experience. (In Carnap and Charles W. Morris` terminology, empirical meaning falls under pragmatics, while linguistic meaning under semantics.) Lewis argues against the logical positivist who shut their eyes to precisely that which properly confirms a sentence, namely the content of experience.

Epistemology
Lewis (1929), Mind and the World Order, is now seen as one of the most important 20th century works in epistemology. Since 2005, following Murray Murphey`s book about Lewis and pragmatism, Lewis has been included among the American pragmatists.[19] Lewis was an early exponent of coherentism, particularly as supported by probability observations such as those advocated by Thomas Bayes.[20]

He was the first to employ the term `qualia`, popularized by his doctoral student Nelson Goodman, in its generally agreed modern sense.[6]

Ethics and aesthetics
Lewis`s late writings on ethics include the monographs Lewis (1955, 1957) and the posthumous collection Lewis (1969). From 1950 until his death, he wrote many drafts of chapters of a proposed treatise on ethics, which he did not live to complete. These drafts are included in the Lewis papers held at Stanford University.

Lewis (1947) contains two chapters on aesthetics and the philosophy of art.

OD 27.4. DO 6.5 SAM NA PUTU. SLANJE I LIČNO PREUZIMANJE JE MOGUĆE POSLE POVRATKA SA PUTA.


Kada kliknete na KUPI ODMAH i naručite predmet automatski ćete dobiti poruku sa svim podacima za uplatu.

OBAVEŠTENJE ZA KUPCE SA KOSOVA I METOHIJE!!!
Slanje knjiga na Kosovo je moguće samo na rizik kupca. U jednom trenutku je bilo problema na administrativnoj liniji, ne znam kakva je situacija sad.

Knjige starije od 50 godina, kao i knjige objavljene ove godine ne šaljem u inostranstvo zbog komplikovane carinske procedure.


Predmet: 72616737
Clarence Irving (C.I.) Lewis was perhaps the most important American academic philosopher active in the 1930s and 1940s. He made major contributions in epistemology and logic, and, to a lesser degree, ethics. Lewis was also a key figure in the rise of analytic philosophy in the United States, both through the development and influence of his own writings and through his influence, direct and indirect, on graduate students at Harvard, including some of the leading analytic philosophers of the last half of the 20th century.

Logic
Lewis studied logic under his eventual Ph.D. thesis supervisor, Josiah Royce, and is a principal architect of modern philosophical logic. In 1912, two years after the publication of the first volume of Principia Mathematica, Lewis began publishing articles[citation needed] taking exception to Principia` s pervasive use of material implication, more specifically, to Bertrand Russell`s reading of a→b as `a implies b.` Lewis restated this criticism in his reviews[citation needed] of both editions of Principia Mathematica. Lewis`s reputation as a promising young logician was soon assured.

Material implication (the rule of inference which claims that stating `P implies Q` is equivalent to stating `Q OR not P`) allows a true consequent to follow from a false antecedent (so if P is not true still Q may be true since you only stated what a true P implies, but did not state what is implied if P is untrue).

Lewis proposed to replace the usage of material implication during discussions involving logic with the term strict implication, by which a (contingently) false antecedent, which is false but could have been true, does not always strictly imply a (contingently) true consequent, which is true but could have been false. The same logical result is implied, but in a clearer and more explicit way. Stating strictly that P implies Q is explicitly not stating what the untrue P implies. And therefor if P is not true, Q may be true, but may be false as well.[11]

As opposed to material implication, in strict implication the statement is not primitive - it is not defined in positive terms, but rather in the combined terms of negation, conjunction, and a prefixed unary intensional modal operator, {\displaystyle \Diamond }\Diamond . The following is its formal definition:

If X is a formula with a classical bivalent truth value
(which must be either true or false),
then {\displaystyle \Diamond }\Diamond X can be read as `X is possibly true`.[11]
Lewis then defined `A strictly implies B` as `{\displaystyle \neg \Diamond }\neg \Diamond (A{\displaystyle \land \neg }{\displaystyle \land \neg }B)`.[12] Lewis`s strict implication is now a historical curiosity, but the formal modal logic in which he grounded that notion is the ancestor of all modern work on the subject. Lewis` {\displaystyle \Diamond }\Diamond notation is still standard, but current practice usually takes its dual, the square notation {\displaystyle \square }\square , meaning `necessity`, which is stating a primitive notion, while the diamond notation, {\displaystyle \Diamond }\Diamond , is left as a defined (derived) meaning. With square notation `A strictly implies B` is simply written as {\displaystyle \square }\square (A→B), which states explicitly that we are only implying the truth of B when A is true, and we are not implying anything about when B can be false, nor what A implies if it is false, in which case B can be false or B can just as well be true.[11]

His first published monograph about advances in logic since the time of Leibniz, A Survey of Symbolic Logic (1918), culminating a series of articles written since 1900, went out of print after selling several hundred copies. At the time of its publication, it included the only discussion in English of the logical writings of Charles Sanders Peirce.[13] This book followed Russell`s 1900 monograph on Leibnitz, and in later editions he removed a section that seemed similar to it.[14][15]

Lewis went on to devise modal logic which he described in his next book Symbolic Logic (1932) as possible formal analyses of the alethic modalities, modes of logical truth such as necessity, possibility and impossibility.

Several amended versions of his first book `A Survey of Symbolic Logic` have been written over the years, designated as S1 to S5, the last two, S4 and S5, generated much mathematical and philosophical interest, sustained to the present day and are the beginnings of what became the field of normal modal logic.[11]

Pragmatist but no positivist
Around 1930, with the introduction of logical empiricism to America by German and Austrian philosophers fleeing Europe under Nazi Germany, American philosophy went through a turning point.

This new doctrine, with its emphasis on scientific models of knowledge and on the logical analysis of meaning, soon became dominant, challenging American philosophers such as Lewis who held a naturalistic or pragmatic approach.[16]

Lewis was perceived as a logical empiricist, but actually differed with it on some major points, rejecting logical positivism, which is the notion that all genuine knowledge is derived solely from sensory experience as interpreted through reason and logic, and rejecting physicalism with its notion that the mind along with its experience is actually equivalent to physical entities such as the brain and the body. He held that experience should be analyzed separately, and that semiotic value does have cognitive significance.[16]

Reflecting on the differences between pragmatism and positivism, Lewis devised the notion of cognitive structure, concluding that any significant knowledge must come from experience. Semiotic value, accordingly, is the way of representing this knowledge, which is stored for deciding future conduct.

Charles Sanders Peirce the founder of pragmaticism saw the world as a system of signs. Therefore scientific research was a branch of semiotics, primarily needing to be analyzed and justified in semiotic terms, before actually conducting any kind of experiment, and the meaning of meaning must be understood before anything else could be `explained`. This included analyzing and studying what experience itself is.[17] In Mind and the World Order (1929) Lewis explained that Peirce`s `pragmatic test` of significance should be understood with Peirce`s own limitation which prescribed meaning only to what makes a verfiable difference in experience although experience is subjective.

A year later, in Pragmatism and Current Thought (1930) he repeated this but emphasized the subjectiveness of experience. Concepts, according to Lewis` explanation of Pierce, are abstractions in which the experience is to be considered, rather than any `factual` or `immediate` truth.[18]

The validation of the perceived experiences are achieved by doing comparison tests. For example if one person perceives time or weight as double that of the other`s perception, the two perceptions are never truly comparable. Thus a concept is a relational pattern.

Still, by checking the physical attributes which each of the two people assign to their experiences, in this case the weight and time in physical units, it is possible to analyze some part of the experience, and one should not discard that very important aspect of the world as it is experienced.

In one sense, that of connotation, a concept strictly comprises nothing but an abstract configuration of relations. In another sense, its denotation or empirical application, this meaning is vested in a process which characteristically begins with something given and ends with something done in the operation which translates a presented datum into an instrument of prediction and control.

Thus knowledge begins and ends in experience, keeping in mind that the beginning and ending experiences differ.

Furthermore, according to Lewis` interpretation of Pierce, knowledge of something requires that the verifying experience itself be actually experienced as well.

Thus, for the pragmatist, verifiability as an operational definition (or test) of the empirical meaning of a statement requires that the speaker know how to apply that statement, when not to apply it, and that the speaker will be able to trace the consequences of the statement in situations both real and hypothetical.

Lewis firmly objected to the positivist interpretation of value statements as being merely `expressive`, devoid of any cognitive content.

In his 1946 essay Logical Positivism and Pragmatism Lewis set out both his concept of sense meaning, and his thesis that valuation is a form of empirical cognition. He disagreed with verificationism, and preferred the term empirical meaning. Claiming that pragmatism and logical positivism are forms of empiricism.

Lewis argued that there is a deep difference between the seemingly similar concepts of pragmatic meaning and the logical-positivist requirement of verification.

According to Lewis, pragmatism ultimately bases its understanding of meaning on conceivable experience, while positivism reduces the relation between meaning and experience to a matter of logical form. Thus, according to Lewis, the positivist view precisely omits the necessary empirical meaning as it would be called by the pragmatist.

Specifying which observational statements follow from a given sentence, helps us determine the empirical meaning of the given sentence only if the observation statements themselves have an already understood meaning in terms of the experience which the observation statements refer to.

According to Lewis, the logical positivists failed to distinguish between `linguistic` meaning - the logical relations among terms, and `empirical` meaning - the relation that expressions must experience. (In Carnap and Charles W. Morris` terminology, empirical meaning falls under pragmatics, while linguistic meaning under semantics.) Lewis argues against the logical positivist who shut their eyes to precisely that which properly confirms a sentence, namely the content of experience.

Epistemology
Lewis (1929), Mind and the World Order, is now seen as one of the most important 20th century works in epistemology. Since 2005, following Murray Murphey`s book about Lewis and pragmatism, Lewis has been included among the American pragmatists.[19] Lewis was an early exponent of coherentism, particularly as supported by probability observations such as those advocated by Thomas Bayes.[20]

He was the first to employ the term `qualia`, popularized by his doctoral student Nelson Goodman, in its generally agreed modern sense.[6]

Ethics and aesthetics
Lewis`s late writings on ethics include the monographs Lewis (1955, 1957) and the posthumous collection Lewis (1969). From 1950 until his death, he wrote many drafts of chapters of a proposed treatise on ethics, which he did not live to complete. These drafts are included in the Lewis papers held at Stanford University.

Lewis (1947) contains two chapters on aesthetics and the philosophy of art.
72616737 Collected Papers of Clarence Irving Lewis

LimundoGrad koristi kolačiće u statističke i marketinške svrhe. Nastavkom korišćenja sajta smatramo da ste pristali na upotrebu kolačića. Više informacija.